Introduction

Social dilemmas are situations in which selfish interest collides with collective interest. Every individual has an incentive to deviate from the common good, but if all subjects acted selfishly they would all be worse off. Depletion of natural resources, intergroup conflicts, climate protection, security of basic social systems, workplace collaborations and price competition in markets are just some of the fundamental situations that can be modelled by means of a social dilemma. Consequently, understanding how and why cooperation can evolve is of primary importance across all biological and social sciences1,2,3,4,5,6,7,8,9,10,11,12,13,14,15,16,17,18,19.

In modern society, many social dilemmas involve a large number of players: firms trying to sell (approximately) the same product, countries involved in reducing the greenhouse gas emissions, taxpayers, work groups, etc. Yet, little is known about the effect of group size on cooperation. Does group size influence cooperation and, if so, how?

A classical point of view states that cooperation should be more difficult in larger groups: since the increase in the number of people inevitably leads to decreasing individual gains relative to the cost of cooperation, free-riding would be much more pervasive in larger groups: large groups will fail; small groups may succeed2,5. However, others pointed out that the increase in the number of people does not necessarily lead to lower individual gains: the incentive to cooperate can even increase and lead to a positive relation between the size of the group and the level of collective actions20,21.

These two possibilities can be captured using two well-known economic games.

Public Goods Game (PGG)

N ≥ 2 contributors are endowed with y dollars and must simultaneously decide how much, if any, to contribute to a public pool. The total amount in the pot is then multiplied by a constant and evenly redistributed among all players. So the monetary payoff of player i is ui(x1, …, xN) = yxi+γ(x1+…+xN), where xi denotes i's contribution and the ‘marginal return’ γ is assumed to belong to the open interval (, 1).

N-person Prisoner's Dilemma (NPD)

N ≥ 2 agents have the choice of either cooperate (C) or defect (D). To defect means doing nothing, while to cooperate means paying a cost c > 0 to generate a benefit b > c that gets shared by all other players. So, if Ci denotes the number of agents other than i who cooperate, then agent i's payoff is , if i cooperates and , if i defects.

The individual benefit for full cooperation in the PGG is equal to γN and so it increases linearly with the number of players, while the individual cost for cooperation remains constantly equal to y. On the other hand, both the individual benefit for full cooperation, b and the individual cost for cooperation, c, remain constant in the NPD as the number of players increases, but, in order to reach the benefit, one needs more people to cooperate. With the above discussion in mind, we should then observe a positive effect of group size on cooperation in the PGG and a negative effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD.

Experimental research has not helped much so far, though it has partially confirmed this prediction. Some experimental results suggest that contributions to the public good are slowly increasing with the number of players22,23, while others suggest no group size effect24 or even a negative effect25. Overall, the picture that emerges is that group size has a moderate, positive effect on cooperation in PGG: in her meta-analysis, Zelmer26 uses data from 27 PGG experiments, conducted using different parametrisations and procedures and finds a positive, moderate (at the 10% level) effect of group size on contributions. However, these experimental studies have been conducted on iterated games, where long-term strategies and group structure may have played a role in shaping the results.

The effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD is also unclear, but slightly in the opposite direction than the PGG: some studies report no effect27 and others report a negative effect28,32. The only studies regarding one-shot games27,28 have the issue that, together with the group size, they also vary either b or c. Since these latter parameters are known to influence the rate of cooperation in opposite ways29,30,31, it is then difficult to say which parameter has caused which effect. To the best of our knowledge, only one study32 keeps b and c constant while varying the size of the group, but it was conducted on iterated games rather than on one-shot games. In this study the authors vary the size of the group from two to five players and find that two people are more cooperative than three, but three people are statistically as cooperative as four or five people.

The experimental contribution of this paper is to clarify this point: Does group size have an effect on cooperation in the PGG and NPD and, if so, how? Since repetitions may create all sorts of ill-understood noise and spillovers across periods that make it difficult to isolate the effect of the size of a group, we have focused on one-shot games. We have conducted two experiments using the online labour market Amazon Mechanical Turk (AMT)33,34,35, one with the PGG and the other one with the NPD. In each of these studies we have separated the participants in two conditions. In Condition S participants played in small groups and in Condition L they played the same one-shot social dilemma but in large groups. Our results are in line with the ones discussed above. We report a significant negative effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD and a significant positive effect of group size on cooperation in the PGG.

Our paper also provides a theoretical contribution. Since cooperation is typically enforced by means of external controls, such as punishment for defectors or reputation for cooperators36,37,38,39,40,41,42,43, predicting the expected rate of cooperation without forms of external controls would allow to optimise the use of these techniques, besides shedding light on the cognitive basis of human decision-making. Are there theoretical models predicting our findings? We show that our results are inconsistent with both Fehr & Schmidt's44 and (the one parameter version of) Charness & Rabin's45 models, but they are consistent with the cooperative equilibrium model13, which indeed predicts both regularities observed. Moreover, since the cooperative equilibrium is a parameter-free model, we can make a direct comparison between experimental data and predictions. We show that, though the predictions of the cooperative equilibrium model point qualitatively in the same direction as the experimental data, they are quantitatively still quite off. Further research is needed to understand how the model could be improved to fit the experimental data better even from a quantitative point of view.

Experimental results

We recruited US subjects using the online labour market AMT. As in classical lab experiments, AMT workers receive a baseline payment and can earn an additional bonus depending on how they perform in the game. AMT experiments are easy to implement and cheap to realise, since AMT workers are paid a substantially smaller amount of money than people participating in physical lab experiments. Nevertheless, it has been shown that data gathered using AMT agree both qualitatively and quantitatively with those collected in physical labs34,35,46,47.

We conducted two studies: in Study A we investigated the group size effect on the Public Goods game and in Study B we investigated the group size effect on the Prisoner's dilemma. For the PGG we opted for small groups of size four and large groups of size forty; for the NPD we opted for small groups of size two and large groups of size eleven. These particular choices are due to the theoretical predictions presented in the next section. Indeed, the cooperative equilibrium model predicts that the size of the group has a weak positive effect on cooperation in the PGG and so here we opted for a small group (four people) and a very large one (forty people); on the other hand, the cooperative equilibrium predicts a strong (exponential) negative effect of the size of he group on cooperation in the NPD. Thus we opted for a very small group N = 2, because it might be possible that for N > 2 the rate of cooperation decays already so much as to make every statistical analysis insignificant. The choice N = 11 for large groups, was made only because we needed a number such that the benefit for cooperation, that is $0:30, could be easily divided by N − 1.

Study A. Group size effect on cooperation in the Public Goods Game

As in other experimental23,24,25 and theoretical48,49 works, we study group size effect on cooperation in the Public Goods game by keeping the marginal return for cooperation γ fixed and increasing the size of the group. Participants earned $0.30 for participation and were randomly assigned to either of two conditions. In Condition S (as in small), they were asked to play a four-player PGG with endowment y = $0.10 and constant marginal return γ = 0.5; in Condition L (as in large), they were asked to play a forty-player PGG with the same endowment and marginal return. After the instructions, participants were asked to answer four comprehension questions. Subjects failing any of them were automatically excluded from the game. Exact full instructions are reported in the Method section.

62 subjects (31% female, average age 29:1) passed the comprehension questions in Condition S and 66 subjects (51% female, mean age 28.9) passed the comprehension questions in Condition L. In AMT experiments with comprehension questions it is virtually impossible to stop the experiment when a precise number of participants is reached. In order to compute the payoffs (for instance) in Condition L, we randomly created two groups of forty people each and we computed the payoffs. Clearly some of the participants belonged to both groups. For these participants we randomly selected either of the two payoffs to be their final bonus.

Table 1 reports all relevant statistics. SEM denotes the standard error of the mean. It is clear that increasing the group size has the effect that more and more people contribute to the public good. The visual impression is confirmed by the Wilcoxon rank-sum test (P = 0.0002).

Table 1 Descriptive statistics of Study 1. Public Goods Game with 4 players (Condition S) versus PGG with 40 players (Condition L). In both conditions, the maximum possible contribution was $0.10 and the marginal return was γ = 0.5. The results show clearly that the larger group is much more cooperative than the smaller group and this is confirmed by the statistical analysis, showing that the means are signifcantly different (Rank-sum, p = 0.0002)

Study B. Group size effect on cooperation in the N-person Prisoner's Dilemma

As in our first study, also Study B uses US subjects recruited through the online labour market AMT. Participants earned $0.30 for participation and were randomly assigned to either of two conditions. In Condition S, they were asked to play a two-player PD with benefit b = $0.30 and cost c = $0.10. in Condition L, they were asked to play an eleven-player PD with the same benefit and cost. Also here we asked for comprehension questions and we automatically excluded from the game those subjects who fail to correctly answer any of them. Full instructions are reported in the Method section.

75 subjects (28% female, average age 28:8) passed the comprehension questions in Condition S and 78 subjects (32% female, mean age 29.6) passed the comprehension questions in Condition L. Table 2 reports all relevant statistics. SEM denotes the standard error of the mean. It is clear that increasing the group size has the effect that fewer and fewer people cooperate. The visual impression is confirmed by Wilcoxon rank-sum test (P = 0.0404).

Table 2 Descriptive statistics of Study 2. Prisoner's Dilemma with 2 players (Condition S) versus Prisoner's Dilemma with 11 players (Condition L). In both conditions, b = $0.30 and c = $0.10. The results suggest that larger groups are less cooperative than smaller ones. This is confirmed by the statistical analysis, which show that the means are significantly difference (Rank-sum, p = 0.0404)

Theoretical results

The previous section reported experimental results in support of the following two findings: (i) Group size has a positive effect on cooperation in the Public Goods Game; (ii) Group size has a negative effect on cooperation in the N-person Prisoner's Dilemma. Are there mathematical models of human behaviour predicting both these regularities?

Here we first consider two of the most widely used models of human behaviour, the Fehr & Schmidt44 and (a one-parameter version of) the Charness & Rabin's45 models and we show that none of them predict the above regularities. Then we extend the cooperative equilibrium model13 from two-person social dilemmas to some social dilemmas and we show that it in fact predicts both of them. Proofs of the results are postponed to the Supplementary Information.

From now on, we fix the following notation. Given a game , let P denote the set of players, each of which has pure strategy set Si and monetary payoff function ui.

Fehr & Shmidt model

Fehr & Schmidt model44 assumes that, given the strategy profile σ, the utility of player i is

where 0 ≤ βi ≤ αi are individual parameters. Specifically, αi represents the extent to which player i is averse to inequity in the favour of others and βi represents the extent to which player i is averse to inequity in his favour.

Given a population of players, each of which with parameters (αi, βi), we denote by the percentage of people such that Ui(C, …, C, D, C, …, C) ≤ Ui(C, …, C) in the NPD.

Proposition 1. For fixed b and c, the function is decreasing with N.

Similarly, consider the PGG with total endowment normalised to be y = 1, so as full cooperation means to contribute 1 and defection corresponds to contribute 0. Let denote the percentage of people such that Ui(1, …, 1, 0, 1, …, 1) ≤ Ui(1, …, 1).

Proposition 2. For fixed γ, the function is independent of N.

In conclusion, while the results of our Study B are consistent with the Fehr-Schmidt model, those of our Study A are not.

Charness & Rabin's model

We consider the following simple form of the Charness & Rabin model45. Given a strategy profile σ, we assume that player i experiences a tension between self interest and common interest and so he or she has utility

where αi [0, 1] is an individual parameter describing how much player i cares about the total welfare.

As before, we consider a population and we denote the percentage of people i P such that Ui(C, …, C, D, C, …, C) ≤ Ui(D, …, D) in the NPD.

Proposition 3. For fixed b and c the function is independent of N.

Proposition 4. For fixed γ, the function µ(PGG(γ, N)) is increasing with N.

In sum, this one-parametric version of the Charness & Rabin model makes qualitatively the right prediction in the PGG, but not in the NPD.

We mention that the most general form of the Charness & Rabin model takes also into account inequity aversion and uses the utility function

Not surprisingly, this general version makes the right prediction in both the PGG and the NPD (we leave the tedious computation to the reader). What we find surprising, however, is that the ultimate reason for the different predictions is caused by two different effects: the tendency to maximise group welfare favours cooperation in large PGG and inequity aversion prevent cooperation in the NPD.

We now pass to the description of a model which predicts both regularities by appealing to the same effect (tendency to maximise the group welfare) and without using any free parameter. The price to pay is a major technical difficulty and the fact that the model, at the moment, is definable only for what we call highly symmetric games.

Cooperative equilibrium

The cooperative equilibrium is a new parameter-free solution concept for two player social dilemmas, which has been shown to make accurate predictions of average behaviour in one-shot13,50 and iterated51 social dilemmas. It is typically a mixed strategy depending on the payoffs, which organises all classical regularities: The level of cooperation in the Prisoner's Dilemma increases as the cost/benefit ratio decreases; The level of cooperation in the Traveler's dilemma increases as the bonus/penalty decreases; The level of cooperation in the Public Goods Game increases as the constant marginal return increases. We now extend this model to some N-player social dilemmas and show that it predicts also the regularities reported in the Experimental Results section.

The key idea behind the cooperative equilibrium is the assumption that humans do not act a priori as single agents, but they forecast how the game would be played if they formed coalitions and then act so as to maximise their forecast.

A general theory for every normal form game would require to consider all possible coalition structures and deal with the fact that different players may have different forecasts about the same coalition structure. Here we eliminate this problem by restricting to only highly symmetric social dilemmas.

  • Symmetry. All players have the same set of strategies S and for each player i, for each permutation π of the set of players and for each strategy profile (s1, …, sN) SN one has

  • High symmetry. The game is symmetric and has a unique (and symmetric) Nash equilibrium and a unique (and symmetric) profile of strategy maximizing the total welfare.

Given the high level of symmetry of the games under consideration, we consider only the two extremal scenarios: the selfish coalition structure and the fully cooperative coalition structure.

Let P denote the set of players, each of which has pure strategy set S, mixed strategy set and utility function ui. Coalition structures are just partitions of the player set. We denote ps the selfish coalition structure and pc the fully cooperative coalition structure. Every coalition structure p {ps, pc} gives rise to a new game , where players in the same coalition play as a single player aiming to maximise the sum of the payoffs of the players belonging to that coalition. For every highly symmetric social dilemma, has a unique Nash equilibrium, which we denote σp. Fix i P and let j P \ {i} be another player. We denote Ij(p) the maximum payoff that player j can obtain by leaving the coalition structure p. Formally,

Ij(p) will be called the incentive of player j to abandon the coalition structure p

Given a profile of strategies (σ1, …, σN), a strategy is called an i-deviation from (σ1, …, σN) if .

We denote Dj(p) the maximal loss that players j can incur if he decides to leave the coalition structure p to try to achieve his maximal possible gain, but also other players deviate from the coalition structure p to either follow their selfish interests or anticipate player j's deviation. Formally,

where σj runs over the set of strategies such that is maximized and σj runs over the set of profiles of strategies (σk)kj for which there is h such that σh is an h-deviation from either σp or (, σj). Dj(p) is called the disincentive for player j in abandoning the coalition structure p. The number

will be informally interpreted as the probability that player i assigns to the event “player j, knowing that all other players are thinking about playing according to p, abandons the coalition structure p”. In the context of anonymous games, where the reasoning of a player cannot affect the reasoning of another player, we define, for ,

Now to define , which is the probability that nobody abandons the coalition structure, we use the law of total probabilities. Assume, for simplicity, that τi,j(p) does not depend on i and j, as is the case in symmetric games. We find

Using Newton's binomial law we finally find

Now, let be the minimum payoff for player i if nobody abandons the coalition structure p, which is just uip), and, finally, let ei,J(p) be the infimum of payoffs of player i when she plays but at least one player j J \ {i} plays a j-deviation from σp. The forecast of player i associated to the coalition structure p is defined as

Observe that symmetry implies that the forecast vi(p), if p {ps, pc}, actually does not depend on i and so there is a coalition structure (independent of i) which maximises the forecast for all players. Moreover, , for all i, j P. We denote this number and we use it to define common beliefs or, in other words, to make a tacit binding among the players.

Definition 1. The induced game is the same game as except for the set of profiles of strategies: the induced game contains only those strategy profiles σ such that , for all i P.

The induced game does not depend on the maximizing coalition structure, that is, in case of multiple coalition structures maximising the forecast, one can choose one of them casually to define the induced game and this game does not depend on such a choice.

Since the set of strategy profiles in the induced game is convex and compact (and nonempty) one can compute Nash equilibria of the induced game.

Definition 2. A cooperative equilibrium for is a Nash equilibrium of the game .

It has been proven in13 that this model organises all classical observations on two-person social dilemmas: The rate of cooperation in the Prisoner's Dilemma increases as the cost/benefit ratio decreases; the rate of cooperation in the Traveler's dilemma increases as the bonus/penalty decreases; the rate of cooperation in the Public Goods Game increases as the constant marginal return increases. We now show that it organises also the regularities observed in our experiments.

Let PGG(N, γ) denote the Public Goods Game with N players and constant marginal return γ. To simplify the formulas, we assume that the total endowment of each player is normalized to y = 1. Denote

Theorem 1. The only (pure) cooperative equilibrium of the PGG(N, γ) is to contribute

In particular, it is increasing with the variable N.

Let PD(b, c, N) denote the N-person Prisoner's Dilemma with cost c and benefit b. Denote

Theorem 2. The only cooperative equilibrium of PD(b, c, N) predicts cooperation with probability

So cooperation is predicted to decrease with the number of agents.

Comparison between predictions and experimental data

Table 3 summarizes the comparison between the models in consideration. Fehr & Schmidt's model makes qualitatively the right prediction in the NPD but not in the PGG; the one-parameter version of the Charness & Rabin model makes qualitatively the right prediction in the PGG but not in the NPD. The two-parameter version of the Charness & Rabin model makes qualitatively the right prediction for both games, at the price of using two free parameters. The cooperative equilibrium makes qualitatively the right prediction for both games, without using any free parameter. Since the cooperative equilibrium is parameter-free, we can make a direct comparison between its predictions and experimental data. Results are summarised in Table 4 and Table 5. While the qualitative behaviour is well-captured, the quantitative prediction is still quite off. An interesting topic for further research is to understand what can be done to improve the quantitative predictions.

Table 3 Summary of the predictions of the models under consideration. FS denotes the Fehr & Schmidt model, which predicts no group size effect on cooperation in the PGG, a negative effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD and uses two free parameters; CR1 denotes the Charness & Rabin model with only one free parameter; CR2 denotes the Charness & Rabin model with two parameters; finally, CE denotes the cooperative equilibrium model
Table 4 Comparison between predictions of the cooperative equilibrium and experimental data in the PGG. In Condition S, the cooperative equilibrium coincides with the Nash equilibrium. In Condition L, it predicts that players should contribute about 35% of their endowment. CE correctly predicts a positive effect of group size on cooperation
Table 5 Comparison between the prediction of the cooperative equilibrium and experimental data. The cooperative equilibrium coincides with the Nash equilibrium in Condition L and predicts that half of the people cooperate in Condition S. The cooperative equilibrium correctly predicts a negative effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD

Discussion

We have studied how the size of a group influences cooperation in two one-shot social dilemmas, the Public Goods Game and the N-person Prisoner's Dilemma. The reason why we have considered these two games is that we expected opposite results. In the PGG the invidual benefit for full cooperation is equal to γN and so it increases linearly with the size of the group, while the cost of cooperation remains constantly equal to y; in the NPD both the individual benefit for full cooperation b and the cost of cooperation c remain constant, but, in order to reach the benefit, one needs more people to cooperate. This difference suggests that we should see a positive effect of group size on cooperation in the PGG and a negative effect of group size on cooperation in the NPD.

To test this prediction we have conducted two experiments using the online labour market Amazon Mechanical Turk. Our results confirmed it showing that forty players are significantly more efficient in providing the public good than only four players (P = 0.0002) and that two players are significantly more cooperative than eleven in a Prisoner's Dilemma (P = 0.0404).

Although the positive effect of group size on cooperation in the PGG has long been debated26,54, we do not find it to be very surprising. It is indeed predicted by the Charness & Rabin model. Also theoretical research on iterated spatial PGGs shows that group size should have a positive effect on cooperation, at least when the PGG is played on a lattice and, after each round, a vertex can take one of his neighbours' strategy with probability depending on the payoff difference49.

Yet, surprisingly, we have found that neither the Fehr & Schmidt model nor (a one-parameter version of) the Charness & Rabin model predict both the regularities observed. The general form of Charness & Rabin's utility makes the right prediction, at the price of using two free parameters. Moreover, different predictions are due to different causes: tendency to maximise the group welfare favours cooperation in large PGGs and inequity aversion prevents cooperation in large NPDs.

We have then extended the cooperative equilibrium model from two-player social dilemmas to some N-player symmetric games, that we have called highly symmetric. Despite the fact that this model does not use any free parameter, it is able to predict both the above mentioned regularities by appealing to a single cause: tendency to maximise total welfare. The quantitative predictions of the model are not dramatically far from the data we gathered, but, at least in three out of four cases, they are still quite off. More experimental data are needed to understand if and how the model can be improved to fit the data better also from a quantitative point of view. In a one-shot setting, as the one under consideration, it is likely that a substantial proportion of players make computational mistakes when they reason about the strategy they want to choose. Thus, a promising direction of research is to define a sort of quantal cooperative equilibrium in a similar way as the standard notion of quantal response equilibrium52 is defined. Ideally, the quantal cooperative equilibrium would be a one-parameter solution concept where the parameter represents the extent to which the players make mistakes in the computations needed to compute the cooperative equilibrium.

Other research questions are worth being mentioned. One way to look at our experimental results is as follows. By leaving both the cost and the benefit of cooperation constant, the group size has a negative effect on cooperation, while, when the increase in the number of agents correspond to an increase in the benefit of cooperation (or, equivalently, to a decrease in the cost of cooperation), then the size of the group may have a positive effect on cooperation which is ultimately due to the increase of the benefit of cooperation (or to the decrease of the cost of cooperation). Our results thus suggest that the pure effect of the group size on cooperation is negative: more people are less likely to cooperate. The group size might have a positive effect only when it generates an increase of the benefit of cooperation or a decrease of the cost of cooperation. Since the difference between the benefit for cooperation and the cost of cooperation in the Public Goods game can be seen as an externally imposed reward to enforce cooperation, it is interesting to figure out what is the cheapest sequence (parametrized by the size of the group) of rewards that gives rise to a positive effect of the size of the group on cooperation. More precisely, let 1 < bN < N be a non-decreasing sequence of real number. Define the N-player general Public Goods game to be the N-player game where each player can either contribute 0 or 1 and gets monetary payoff

where xj denotes player j's contribution. Our results show that the group size has a positive effect on cooperation when bN increases linearly with the number of players (bN = γN in the standard PGG) and it has a negative effect on cooperation when bN is constant in N (which is essentially equivalent to the NPD). Consequently, there must be a sequence bN of numbers representing the behavioural transition from a negative effect of the group size on cooperation to a positive effect. An interesting question would be to find this sequence.

Our model also predicts existence of strategic situations for which group size has a non-linear effect with intermediate groups being more cooperative. Theorems 1 and 2 indeed imply that a general PGG defined by a sequence bN = γN, for NN0 and , for all N > N0, will have a cooperative equilibrium whose maximum level of cooperation is reached for some intermediate group size. This strategic situation is likely to happen in real-life situations, in which when the number of cooperators reaches a saturation threshold, no additional benefit is created. A concrete example of such a situation has been recently reported in ref. 53. Here the authors report a field study in which intermediate groups were more cooperative than small and large groups. The case reported is that of monitoring the Wolong Nature Reserve, Sichuan Province, China, by means of a number of households. They found that if the number of households is either too small or too large, then the monitoring effort of each household is also small; the monitoring effort of the households is maximized when the number of households is somewhat intermediate.

Other research questions come from looking at some of the predictions made by the cooperative equilibrium model.

  • For fixed N and c, the benefit b has a positive effect on cooperation in the NPD.

  • For fixed N and b, the cost c has a negative effect on cooperation in the NPD.

Confirmation of these two predictions have been recently found in the case of two players29,30,31 and we cannot find any reasonable motivation why they should fail in larger groups.

The model also predicts that, with N fixed, γ has a positive effect on cooperation in the PGG. This fact has been confirmed by several experimental studies on both one-shot and iterated PGGs26,54,55,56,57.

Another highly symmetric social dilemma to which the cooperative equilibrium model can be applied is the Bertrand Competition (BC). In the BC, N ≥ 2 firms compete to sell their identical product. Each of the firms can choose a price between the ‘price floor’ L and the ‘reservation value’ H > L. The firm that chooses the lowest price, say s, sells the product at that price, getting a payoff of s; all other firms get nothing. Ties get split among all firms that made the corresponding price. One easily sees that the only cooperative equilibrium of this game is to set the price

So the cooperative equilibrium makes the prediction that the size of the group has a strong (more than exponential) negative effect on cooperation in the BC. This prediction has been partially confirmed by other experimental studies58,59,60, which have shown that four people are already enough to completely destroy cooperative behaviour. However, these studies concern iterated games and so more experimental evidence would be needed.

On the theoretical side, many questions concerning the model should be addressed, starting from the broad question of extending the cooperative equilibrium model as far as possible, at least to include other relevant social dilemmas such as the Volunteer dilemma61 and the collective-risk social dilemma62. Unfortunately, these social dilemmas possess one of the general characteristics preventing the development of a general theory: in case the game has many (possibly infinite) equilibria, which one should be used as a reference strategy profiles σp to compute incentives and disincentives? Other theoretical questions include: Can the cooperative equilibrium be expressed in terms of classical utility theory through a utility function to be maximised?

Method

The experimental part of this article uses US subjects recruited through Amazon Mechanical Turk. Participants were randomly assigned to one of four experiments using economic games (PGGlarge, PGGsmall, NPDlarge, NPDsmall). After entering the survey, AMT workers were asked to type their Turk ID and a long CAPTCHA-like code. Specifically, in order to filter out lazy participants, we asked them to write the following neutral sentence (taken from Wikipedia) in reverse order.

Morocco has a coast on the Atlantic Ocean that reaches past the Strait of Gibraltar into the Mediterranean Sea. It is bordered by Spain to the north, Algeria to the east and Western Sahara to the south. Since Morocco controls most of Western Sahara, its de facto southern boundary is with Mauritania.

Participants who passed this first test were presented the rules of the game. In Condition PGGsmall they were presented as follows:

You are part of a group of four participants. The amount of money you can earn depends on each of the four participants' decisions.

All participants are given 10 ¢ and each one has to decide how much, if any, to contribute to a pool. Your gain will be what you keep plus half of the total amount contributed by all players.

So, for instance:

  • If everyone contributes all of their money, then you end the game with 20 ¢.

  • If you do not contribute anything and everyone else contributes all of their money, then you end the game with 25 ¢.

  • If no one contributes anything, then you end the game with 10 ¢.

Instructions for Condition PGGlarge were exactly the same, a part from obvious changes. Instructions for Condition NPDsmall were instead presented as follows:

You have been paired with another participant. The amount of money you can earn depends on your and the other participant's decision.

You are both given 10 ¢ and each of you must decide whether to keep it or give it away. Each time a participant gives away their 10 ¢, the other participant earns 30 ¢.

So:

  • If you both decide to give the 10 ¢, you end the game with 30 ¢.

  • If you keep it and the other participant gives it away, you end the game with 40 ¢.

  • If you give it away and the other participant keeps it, you end the game with 0 ¢.

  • If you both keep it, then you end the game with 10 ¢.

Instructions for Condition NPDlarge were exactly the same, a part from obvious changes.

In order to have good quality results, after explaining the rules of the game, we asked four comprehension questions. Participants who failed any of the comprehension questions were automatically excluded from the game. We could do this very easily using the Survey builder Qualtrics, which allows us to use skip logics: programs that automatically end the survey if the correct answer is not selected. Questions were formulated in such a way to make clear the duality between maximising one's own payoff and maximising the others' payoff. Specifically, we asked the following questions.

  • What is the choice you should make to maximise your gain?

  • What is the choice you should make to maximise the other participants' gains?

  • What choice should the other participants make to maximise their own gains?

  • What choice should the other participants make to maximise your gain?

Subjects who passed the comprehension questions were then asked to make their decision. After playing, subjects were asked a few basic demographic questions (gender, age and level of education) and the reason why they made their decision. After this, the survey ended providing the code to claim for the bonus. Participants were also informed that computation and payment of the bonuses would be made at the end of the experiment. No deception was used. Written consent was obtained by all participants and the experiments were approved by the Southampton University Ethics Committee on the Use of Human Subjects in Research and carried out in accordance with the approved guidelines.